Homo sapiens has long sought to set itself apart from animals — that is, apart from every other living species. One of the most enduring attempts to define humanity in a way that distances us from the rest of animal life was Aristotle’s description of the human being as a “political animal.” By this he meant that human beings are the only species that live in the “polis” or city-state, though the term has often been understood to include villages, communes, and other organized social units. Implicit in this definition is the idea that all other animals are not political, that they live altogether outside of internally governed social units.
This supposed freedom
from political strictures has motivated some, such as the 19th-century
anarchist aristocrat Piotr Kropotkin, to take nonhuman animals as a
model for human society. But for the most part the ostensibly
nonpolitical character of animal life has functioned simply to exclude
animals from human consideration as beings with interests of their own.
What might we be
missing when we cut animals off in this way from political
consideration? For one thing, we are neglecting a great number of solid
scientific facts.
There are overwhelming
empirical data revealing, to anyone who is willing to look, complex
social organization across the animal kingdom, including collective
deliberation, division of labor, ritualized conflict resolution, and
other forms of behavior that, when identified in human society, are
deemed political without hesitation. We know that elephants plan
elaborate raids on human settlements to recover the remains of their
slaughtered loved ones. We know that in ant colonies the appearance of
elaborate systems of task-allocation is related directly to the size of
the colony: just as in human society, the more individual members of the
society, the more we may expect to find social differentiation. Thanks
to the primatologist Frans De Waal’s popular work, we are now slowly
warming up to the idea that there is such a thing, at least, as
“chimpanzee politics.”
These are just a few
examples from recent science, and to some extent they build on what we
have known all along but have preferred not to see. Aristotle himself
reports accurately on elephant intelligence and social behavior in the
“History of Animals”; in the “Georgics” Virgil gives a fairly solid
account of the goings-on within beehives. Yet the combined force of
ancient wisdom and recent science will still not do much to convince the
skeptic, who interprets all empirical evidence of animal politics as
pointing only to structures in the animal world that are homologous to
what we see in human society, but that still do not share that magical
je ne sais quoi that makes human society what it is. What we do as human
beings when we deliberate, or love or cooperate, in this line of
thinking, animals do only in an imitative or counterfeit way. They only
“deliberate,” “love” or “cooperate” — in scare quotes.
But there is another
way of understanding animals as political that even the most defiant
human-exceptionalist cannot dispute: not as separated out into their own
discrete political societies, each according to its kind, but rather as
part of a single, global political formation that includes, notably but
not exclusively, human beings. Some recent political philosophy, in
fact, is starting to approach its subject from just such a trans-species
perspective. In their groundbreaking 2011 book, “Zoopolis: A Political
Theory of Animal Rights,” Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka argue
compellingly that animal rights theory has been limited to the extent
that it has emphasized only negative rights of animals, a category that
is conceived as universal and without any distinctions of moral
significance within it. They argue instead that theorists would do well
to focus on relational obligations that human beings come to have to
animals that figure in different ways in human society. For them,
nonhuman animals belong to the polis, too.
The ways animals figure in society — vermin, livestock, pets, wildlife, beasts of burden, seeing-eye dogs, and so on — mirrors the different ways in which different human groups are endowed with or deprived of their rights.
If this perspective
seems tangential to the central concerns of political philosophy, it
might be worthwhile to consider that, from a historical perspective, the
development of human political formations seems to have been closely
connected with changes in the way human groups related to certain animal
species. In particular, there is increasing evidence for canine
domestication contemporaneous with what is often called the “great leap
forward” in the Upper Paleolithic, a period that witnessed the
appearance of such features of human behavioral modernity as symbolic
thought and religious ritual. More important, many thousands of years
later the first sedentary, proto-urban cultures arose in the Levant in
tandem with the rise of livestock domestication (and also, of course, of
agriculture). The emergence of state structures thus seems connected
not only to the rise of grain storage, and therefore also of private
property and of social inequality and slavery, but also to the systemic
domination of certain animals by human beings. It is hard to say what
exactly civilization is, but one thing seems certain: there could be no
civilization without domestication.
The domination of
animals went together with their symbolic incorporation into human
society. We know that without exception early livestock-holding
societies took the animals they dominated to be absolutely central to
their own social existence as human beings. For the first several
millenniums of city living, long before Aristotle wrote, human beings
did not yet think of themselves as the only political animals.
The Greeks’ exclusion
of animals from the domain of the political (and also from the pantheon
of gods, in contrast with their Near Eastern neighbors) would have
consequences that can still be felt today in the way we conceive of the
scope of the political. As in Sumer and ancient Greece, animals continue
to play a vital role in human society. Notably, they are raised and
slaughtered by the billions, and their meat is sold and consumed. Yet
their presence in society is conceived as political for the most part
only to the extent that rules are made about where they may be raised,
how they may be sold, at what price, and so on. They are generally not
conceived as political in the sense of being themselves members or
participants in a trans-species polis.
Manifestly, however,
the ways animals figure in society, and what may be done to or with the
animals representing different social categories — vermin, livestock,
pets, wildlife, beasts of burden, seeing-eye dogs, and so on — mirrors
the different ways in which different human groups are endowed with or
deprived of their rights. Endowing and depriving different human groups
of rights and resources is, in one understanding of the term, precisely
what we mean when we speak of politics.
In his remarkable 1999
work of quasi-fiction, “The Lives of Animals,” J. M. Coetzee has his
protagonist, the Australian author Elizabeth Costello, give a lecture at
an American university on the subject of the book’s title. She says a
number of ostensibly radical things about the horrors human beings
commit against animals. She makes the dreaded comparison to the
Holocaust, which so often appears to be the last resort of desperate
rhetoricians. Among the audience members is Abraham Stern, a Holocaust
survivor. He sends her a note explaining why he refuses to attend that
evening’s dinner: “If Jews were treated like cattle, it does not follow
that cattle are treated like Jews. The inversion insults the memory of
the dead.”
Whatever else the
actions of the Nazis were, they were political. The German state,
representing the will of a majority of the German people, deprived the
Jews of their rights, dehumanized them as vermin, and sought to
exterminate them. These efforts were political, not in the sense that
they occurred within a smoothly functioning deliberative democracy, but
in the sense that they sought, by extreme violence, to determine once
and for all the true bounds of the polis, to settle who was rightfully a
member of society and who was necessarily excluded.
Stern is right to take
offense at Costello’s comparison. It does not automatically follow from
the fact that a group of humans and a group of animals are treated in
externally similar ways, that the treatment has the same moral
significance in each case. However, it does not insult the memory of
those human beings who have been deprived of their rights and excluded
from consideration as political subjects to note that, as a matter of
fact, the animals that play a central role in our society are
systematically excluded from the polis, from the scope of the political.
Their exclusion is what makes possible the perpetuation of the system
of mass slaughter as if this were not an expression of our society’s
political will.
Things were not always
this way. Although human beings have always killed animals, the
evidence strongly suggests that in hunter-gatherer and early pastoral
societies, the animals that were killed were not held to be morally
irrelevant, nor were they held to be external interlopers in the
human polis. Nor is there any compelling reason things should
remain as they are. Perhaps it is time to rethink the boundaries of the
political.
No comments:
Post a Comment