Translate

Sunday, June 3, 2018

Presocratic Philosophy



    The Presocratics were 6th and 5th century BCE Greek thinkers who introduced a new way of inquiring into the world and the place of human beings in it. They were recognized in antiquity as the first philosophers and scientists of the Western tradition. This article is a general introduction to the most important Presocratic philosophers and the main themes of Presocratic thought. More detailed discussions can be found by consulting the articles on these philosophers (and related topics) in the SEP (listed below). The standard collection of texts for the Presocratics is that by H. Diels revised by W. Kranz (abbreviated as DK). In it, each thinker is assigned an identifying chapter number (e.g., Heraclitus is 22, Anaxagoras 59); then the reports from ancient authors about that thinker's life and thought are collected in a section of “testimonies” (A) and numbered in order, while the passages the editors take to be direct quotations are collected and numbered in a section of “fragments” (B). Alleged imitations in later authors are sometimes added in a section labeled C. Thus, each piece of text can be uniquely identified: DK 59B12.3 identifies line 3 of Anaxagoras fragment 12; DK 22A1 identifies testimonium 1 on Heraclitus.


    1. Who Were the Presocratic Philosophers?

    Our understanding of the Presocratics is complicated by the incomplete nature of our evidence. Most of them wrote at least one “book” (short pieces of prose writing, or, in some cases, poems), but no complete work survives. Instead, we are dependent on later philosophers, historians, and compilers of collections of ancient wisdom for disconnected quotations (fragments) and reports about their views (testimonia). In some cases, these sources had direct access to the works of the Presocratics, but in many others, the line is indirect and often depends on the work of Hippias, Aristotle, Theophrastus, Simplicius, and other ancient philosophers who did have such access. The sources for the fragments and testimonia made selective use of the material available to them, in accordance with their own special, and varied, interests in the early thinkers. (For analyses of the doxographic tradition, and the influence of Aristotle and Theophrastus on later sources, see Mansfeld 1999, Runia 2008, and Mansfeld and Runia 1997, 2009a, and 2009b.) Although any account of a Presocratic thinker has to be a reconstruction, we should not be overly pessimistic about the possibility of reaching a historically responsible understanding of these early Greek thinkers.
    Calling this group “Presocratic philosophers” raises certain difficulties. The term, coined in the eighteenth century, was made current by Hermann Diels in the nineteenth, and was meant to mark a contrast between Socrates who was interested in moral problems, and his predecessors, who were supposed to be primarily concerned with cosmological and physical speculation. “Presocratic,” if taken strictly as a chronological term, is not accurate, for the last of them were contemporaneous with Socrates and even Plato. Moreover, several of the early Greek thinkers explored questions about ethics and the best way to live a human life. The term may also suggest that these thinkers are somehow inferior to Socrates and Plato, of interest only as their predecessors, and its suggestion of archaism may imply that philosophy only becomes interesting when we arrive at the classical period of Plato and Aristotle. Some scholars now deliberately avoid the term, but if we take it to refer to the early Greek thinkers who were not influenced by the views of Socrates, whether his predecessors or contemporaries, there is probably no harm in using it. (For discussions of the notion of Presocratic philosophy, see Long's introduction in Long 1999, Laks 2006, and the articles in Laks and Louguet 2002.)
    A second problem lies in referring to these thinkers as philosophers. That is almost certainly not how they could have described themselves. While it is true that Heraclitus says that “those who are lovers of wisdom must be inquirers into many things” (22B35), the word he uses, philosophos, does not have the special sense that it acquires in the works of Plato and Aristotle, when the philosopher is contrasted with both the ordinary person and other experts, including the sophist (particularly in Plato), or in the resulting modern sense in which we can distinguish philosophy from physics or psychology; yet the Presocratics certainly saw themselves as set apart from ordinary people and also from others (certain of the poets and historical writers, for example, as we can see from Xenophanes and Heraclitus) who were their predecessors and contemporaries. As the fragment from Heraclitus shows, the early Greek philosophers thought of themselves as inquirers into many things, and the range of their inquiry was vast. They had views about the nature of the world, and these views encompass what we today call physics, chemistry, geology, meteorology, astronomy, embryology, and psychology (and other areas of natural inquiry), as well as theology, metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. In the earliest of the Presocratics, the Milesians, it can indeed be difficult to discern the strictly philosophical aspects of the views in the evidence available to us. Nevertheless, despite the danger of misunderstanding and thus underestimating these thinkers because of anachronism, there is an important sense in which it is quite reasonable to refer to them as philosophers. That sense is inherent in Aristotle's view (see, e.g., Metaphysics I, Physics I, De Anima I, On Generation and Corruption I): these thinkers were his predecessors in a particular sort of inquiry, and even though Aristotle thinks that they were all, for one reason or another, unsuccessful and even amateurish, he sees in them a similarity such that he can trace a line of continuity of both subject and method from their work to his own. The questions that the early Greek philosophers asked, the sorts of answers that they gave, and the views that they had of their own inquiries were the foundation for the development of philosophy as it came to be defined in the work of Plato and Aristotle and their successors. Perhaps the fundamental characteristic is the commitment to explain the world in terms of its own inherent principles.
    By contrast, consider the 7th century BCE poem of Hesiod, his Theogony (genealogy of the gods). Hesiod tells the traditional story of the Olympian gods, beginning with Chaos, a vague divine primordial entity or condition. From Chaos, a sequence of gods is generated, often by sexual congress, but sometimes no cause for their coming to be is given. The divine figures that thus arise are often connected with a part of the physical universe, or with some aspect of human experience, so his theogony is also a cosmogony (an account of the generation of the world). The divinities (and the associated parts of the world) come to be and struggle violently among themselves; finally Zeus triumphs and establishes and maintains an order of power among the others. Hesiod's world is one in which the major divinities are individuals who behave like super-human beings (Gaia or earth, Ouranos or sky, Cronos — an unlocated regal power, Zeus); some of the others are personified characteristics (e.g., Momus, blame; and Dusnomia, lawlessness). For the Greeks, the fundamental properties of divinity are immortality (they are not subject to death) and great power (as part of the cosmos or in managing events), and each of Hesiod's characters has these properties (even though in the story some are defeated, and seem to be destroyed). Hesiod's story is like a vast Hollywood-style family history, with envy, rage, love, and lust all playing important parts in the coming-to-be of the world as we know it. The earliest rulers of the universe are violently overthrown by their offspring (Ouranos is overthrown by Cronos, Cronos by Zeus). Zeus insures his continued power by swallowing his first consort Metis (counsel or wisdom); by this he prevents the predicted birth of rivals and acquires her attribute of wisdom (Theogony 886–900). In a second poem, Works and Days, Hesiod pays more attention to human beings, telling the story of earlier, greater creatures who died out or were destroyed by themselves or Zeus. Humans were created by Zeus, are under his power, and are subject to his judgment and to divine intervention for either good or ill. (A good discussion of the Hesiodic myths in relation to Presocratic philosophy can be found in McKirahan 2011. Burkert 2008 surveys influence from the east on the development of Presocratic philosophy, especially the myths, astronomy, and cosmogony of the Babylonians, Persians, and Egyptians.)
    Hesiod's world, like Homer's, is one that is god-saturated, where the gods may intervene in all aspects of the world, from the weather to mundane particulars of human life, acting on the ordinary world order, in a way that humans, limited as they are by time, location, and narrow powers of perception, must accept but cannot ultimately understand. The Presocratics reject this account, instead seeing the world as a kosmos, an ordered natural arrangement that is inherently intelligible and not subject to supra-natural intervention. A striking example is Xenophanes 21B32: “And she whom they call Iris, this too is by nature cloud / purple, red, and greeny yellow to behold.” Iris, the rainbow, traditional messenger of the gods, is after all, not supra-natural, not a sign from the gods on Olympus who are outside of and immune from the usual world order; rather it is, in its essence, colored cloud.
    Calling the Presocratics philosophers also suggests that they share a certain outlook with one another; an outlook that can be contrasted with that of other early Greeks. Although scholars disagree about the extent of the divergence between the early Greek philosophers and their non-philosophical predecessors and contemporaries, it is evident that Presocratic thought exhibits a difference not only in its understanding of the nature of the world, but also in its view of the sort of explanation of it that is possible. This is clear in Heraclitus. Although Heraclitus asserts that those who love wisdom must be inquirers into many things, inquiry alone is not sufficient. At 22B40 he rebukes four of his predecessors: “Much learning does not teach understanding; else it would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again Xenophanes and Hecataeus.” Heraclitus' implicit contrast is with himself; in 22B1 he suggests that he alone truly understands all things, because he grasps the account that enables him to “distinguish each thing in accordance with its nature” and say how it is. For Heraclitus there is an underlying principle that unites and explains everything. It is this that others have failed to see and understand. According to Heraclitus, the four have amassed a great deal of information — Hesiod was a traditional source of information about the gods, Pythagoras was renowned for his learning and especially views about how one ought to live, Xenophanes taught about the proper view of the gods and the natural world, Hecataeus was an early historian — but because they have failed to grasp the deeper significance of the facts available to them, their unconnected bits of knowledge do not constitute understanding. Just as the world is a kosmos, an ordered arrangement, so human knowledge of that world must be ordered in a certain way.

    2. The Milesians

    In his account of his predecessors' searches for “causes and principles” of the natural world and natural phenomena, Aristotle says that Thales of Miletus (a city in Ionia, on the west coast of what is now Turkey) was the first to engage in such inquiry. He seems to have lived around the beginning of the 6th c. BCE. Aristotle mentions that some people, before Thales, placed great importance on water, but he credits Thales with declaring water to be the first cause (Metaphysics 983b27–33), and he then later raises the question of whether perhaps Hesiod was the first to look for a cause of motion and change (984b23ff.). These suggestions are rhetorical: Aristotle does not seriously imply that those he mentions are engaged in the same sort of inquiry as he thinks Thales was. Two other Greek thinkers from this very early period, Anaximander and Anaximenes, were also from Miletus, and although the ancient tradition that the three were related as master and pupil may not be correct, there are enough fundamental similarities in their views to justify treating them together.
    The tradition claims that Thales predicted a solar eclipse in 585 BC (11A5), introduced geometry into Greece from Egypt (11A11), and produced some engineering marvels. Anaximander is reported to have invented the gnomon (the raised piece of a sundial whose shadow marks time); to have created a sphere of the heavens serving as an astronomical and cosmological model (12A1); and to have been the first to draw a map of the inhabited world (12A6). Regardless of whether these reports are correct (and in the case of Thales' prediction they almost certainly are not), they indicate something important about the Milesians: their interests in measuring and explaining celestial and terrestrial phenomena were as strong as their concern with the more abstract inquiries into the causes and principles of substance and change attributed to them by Aristotle (Algra 1999, White 2002 and 2008). They did not see so-called “scientific” and “philosophical” questions as belonging to separate disciplines, requiring distinct methods of inquiry. The assumptions and principles that we (along with Aristotle) see as constituting the philosophical foundations of their theories are, for the most part, implicit in the claims that they make. Nevertheless, it is legitimate to treat the Milesians as having philosophical views, even though no clear statements of these views or specific arguments for them can be found in the surviving fragments and testimonia.
    Aristotle's comments do not sound as if they were based on first-hand knowledge of Thales' views, and the doxographical reports say that Thales did not write a book. Yet Aristotle is confident that Thales belongs, even if honorifically, to that group of thinkers that he calls “inquirers into nature” and distinguishes him from earlier poetical “myth-makers.” In Book I of the Metaphysics, Aristotle claims that the earliest of these, among whom he places the Milesians, explained things only in terms of their matter (Met. I.3 983b6–18). This claim is anachronistic in that it presupposes Aristotle's own novel view that a complete explanation must encompass four factors: what he called the material, efficient, formal, and final causes. Yet there is something in what Aristotle says. Aristotle links Thales' claim that the world rests on water with the view that water was the archē, or fundamental principle, and he adds that “that from which they come to be is a principle of all things” (983b24–25; 11A12). He suggests that Thales chose water because of its fundamental role in coming-to-be, nutrition, and growth, and claims that water is the origin of the nature of moist things.
    Aristotle's general assertion about the first thinkers who gave accounts of nature (and his specific discussion of Thales' reliance on water as a first principle) brings out a difficulty in interpreting the early Presocratics. According to Aristotle's general account, the Presocratics claimed that there was a single enduring material stuff that is both the origin of all things and their continuing nature. Thus, on this view, when Thales says that the first principle is water, he should be understood as claiming both that the original state of things was water and that even now (despite appearances), everything is really water in some state or another. The change from the original state to the present one involves changes in the material stuff such that although it may not now appear to be water everywhere (but seems to be airier or earthier than water in its usual state, or its original one), there is no transformation of water into a different kind of stuff (air or earth, for instance). Yet, when Aristotle comes to give what details he can of Thales' view, he suggests only that for Thales, water was the first principle because everything comes from water. Water, then, was perhaps the original state of things for Thales, and water is a necessary condition for everything that is generated naturally, but Aristotle's summary of Thales' view does not imply that Thales claimed that water endures through whatever changes have occurred since the original state, and now just has some new or additional properties. Thales may well have thought that certain characteristics of the original water persisted: in particular its capacity for motion (which must have been innate in order to generate the changes from the original state). This is suggested by Thales' reported claims that the lodestone (with its magnetic properties) and amber (which when rubbed exhibits powers of attraction through static electricity) have souls and that all things are full of gods. Aristotle surmises that Thales identified soul (that which makes a thing alive and thus capable of motion) with something in the whole universe, and so supposed that everything was full of gods (11A22)—water, or soul, being a divine natural principle. Certainly the claim that the lodestone has soul suggests this account. Given that the analysis of change (both qualitative and substantial) in terms of a substratum that gains and loses properties is Aristotelian (although perhaps foreshadowed in Plato), it is not surprising that the earlier views were unclear on this issue, and it is probable that the Milesian view did not clearly distinguish the notions of an original matter and an enduring underlying stuff (Graham 2006).
    The reports about Thales show him employing a certain kind of explanation: ultimately the explanation of why things are as they are is grounded in water as the basic stuff of the universe and the changes that it undergoes through its own inherent nature. In this, Thales marks a radical change from all other previous sorts of accounts of the world (both Greek and non-Greek). Like the other Presocratics, Thales sees nature as a complete and self-ordering system, and sees no reason to call on divine intervention from outside the natural world to supplement his account—water itself may be divine, but it is not something that intervenes in the natural world from outside (Gregory, 2013). While the evidence for Thales' naturalistic account is circumstantial, this attitude can be directly verified for Anaximander.
    In the one fragment that can be securely attributed to Anaximander (although the extent of the implied quotation is uncertain), he emphasizes the orderly nature of the universe, and indicates that the order is internal rather than imposed from outside. Simplicius, a 6th c. CE commentator on Aristotle's Physics, writes:
    Of those who say that [the first principle] is one and moving and indefinite, Anaximander, son of Praxiades, a Milesian who became successor and pupil to Thales, said that the indefinite (to apeiron) is both principle (archē) and element (stoicheion) of the things that are, and he was the first to introduce this name of the principle. He says that it is neither water nor any other of the so-called elements, but some other indefinite (apeiron) nature, from which come to be all the heavens and the worlds in them; and those things, from which there is coming-to-be for the things that are, are also those into which is their passing-away, in accordance with what must be. For they give penalty (dikê) and recompense to one another for their injustice (adikia) in accordance with the ordering of time—speaking of them in rather poetical terms. It is clear that having seen the change of the four elements into each other, he did not think it fit to make some one of these underlying subject, but something else, apart from these. (Simplicius, Commentary on Aristotle's Physics 24, lines 13ff. = 12A9 and B1)[1]
    Thus, there is an original (and originating) indefinite stuff, from which all the heavens and the worlds in them come to be. This claim probably means that the original state of the universe was an indefinitely large mass of stuff that was also indefinite in its character.[2] This stuff then gave rise through its own inherent power to the ingredients that themselves constitute the world as we perceive it.
    A testimony about Anaximander from Pseudo-Plutarch (12A10) says that “Something productive of hot and cold was separated off from the eternal at the genesis of this world and from this a sphere of flame grew around the air around the earth like the bark around a tree.” Neither the cause nor the precise process of separation is explained, but it is probable that Anaximander would have thought of motion as innate and so that the original source of change was part of the character of the indefinite itself. The passage from Simplicius shows that Anaximander does not think that the eternal indefinite stuff gives rise directly to the cosmos as we know it. Rather, relying on a semi-biological model, Anaximander claims that the apeiron somehow generates the opposites hot and cold. Hot and cold are themselves stuffs with powers; and it is the actions of these stuffs/powers that produce the things that come to be in our world. The opposites act on, dominate, and contain each other, producing a regulated structure; thus things pass away into those things from which they came to be. It is this structured arrangement that Anaximander refers to when he speaks of justice and reparation. Over the course of time, the cycles of the seasons, the rotations of the heavens, and other sorts of cyclical change (including coming-to-be and passing-away) are regulated and thus form a system. This system, ruled by the justice of the ordering of time is in sharp contrast with the chaotic and capricious world of the personified Greek gods who interfere in the workings of the heavens and in the affairs of human beings (Kahn 1985a, Vlastos 1947, Guthrie 1962).
    The pattern that can be seen in Thales and Anaximander of an original stuff giving rise to the phenomena of the cosmos continues in the views of the third of the Milesians, Anaximenes. He replaces Anaximander's apeiron with air, thus eliminating the first stage of the coming-to-be of the cosmos (the something productive of hot and cold). Rather, he returns to an originating stuff more like Thales' water. In 13A5, Aristotle's associate Theophrastus, quoted by Simplicius, speculates that Anaximenes chose air because he agreed that a basic principle must be neutral (as Anaximander's apeiron is) but not so lacking in properties that it seems to be nothing at all. Air can apparently take on various properties of color, temperature, humidity, motion, taste, and smell. Moreover, according to Theophrastus, Anaximenes explicitly states the natural mechanism for change; it is the condensation and rarefaction of air that naturally determine the particular characters of the things produced from the originating stuff. Rarified, air becomes fire; more and more condensed, it becomes progressively wind, cloud, water, earth, and finally stones. “The rest,” says Theophrastus, “come to be from these.” Plutarch says that condensation and rarefaction are connected with cooling and heating, and he gives the example of breath (13B1). Releasing air from the mouth with compressed lips produces cool air (as in cooling soup by blowing on it), but relaxed lips produce warm air (as when one blows on cold hands to warm them up).
    Does the originating stuff persist through the changes that it undergoes in the generating processes? Aristotle's account suggests that it does, that Anaximenes, for instance, would have thought that stone was really air, although in an altered state, just as we might say that ice is really water, cooled to a point where it goes from a liquid to a solid state. Because the water does not cease to be water when it is cooled and becomes ice, it can return to a liquid when heated and then become a gas when more heat is applied. On this view, the Milesians were material monists, committed to the reality of a single material stuff that undergoes many alterations but persists through the changes (Barnes 1979, Guthrie 1962, Sedley 2007 and 2009). Yet there are reasons to doubt that this was actually the Milesian view. It presumes that the early Greek thinkers anticipated Aristotle's general theory that change requires enduring underlying substances that gain and lose properties. The earliest Greeks thought more in terms of powers (Vlastos 1947, Heidel 1906), and the metaphysical problem of what it is to be a substance was yet to be formulated. Clearly the Milesians were interested in the originating stuff from which the world developed (Anaximander and Anaximenes are explicit about transformations of such an eternal originating stuff), but the view that this endured as a single substratum may not have been theirs. Rather, it has been suggested by Graham (1997 and 2006; Mourelatos 2008) that the Milesians were not, in Aristotle's sense, material monists. On this view, the original/originating stuff is transformed into other substances. Anaximenes, for instance, may have thought that the change from air to water does not involve the persistence of air as any sort of substratum. There is no special role that air plays in the theory except that it is the originating stuff and so first in an analysis of the law-like cyclical changes that produce various stuffs as the cosmos develops (Graham 2006, ch. 4). Such an interpretation suggests how different the Milesian conception of the world is from Aristotle's.

    3. Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus

    Living in the last years of the 6th c. and the beginning of the 5th, Xenophanes and Heraclitus continue the Milesian interest in the nature of the physical world, and both offer cosmological accounts; yet they go further than the Milesians not only through their focus on the human subject and the expanded range of their physical explanations, but by investigating the nature of inquiry itself. Both explore the possibility of human understanding and question its limits. Recent work on Xenophanes' epistemology and his cosmology has made much of his scientific work clearer and more impressive (Lesher 1992, Mourelatos 2008). He has, to a great extent, been rescued from his traditional status as a minor traveling poet-sage who railed against the glorification of athletes and made some interesting comments about the relativity of human conceptions of the gods. Instead, he has come to be seen as an original thinker in his own right who influenced later philosophers trying to characterize the realms of the human and the divine, and exploring the possibility that human beings can gain genuine knowledge and wisdom, i.e., are able to have a god's eye view of things and understand them (Curd 2013, Mogyoródi 2002 and 2006).
    Xenophanes claims that all meteorological phenomena are clouds, colored, moving, incandescent: rainbow, St. Elmo's Fire, the sun, the moon. Clouds are fed by exhalations from the land and sea (mixtures of earth and water). The motions of earth and water, and hence of clouds, account for all the things we find around us. His explanations of meteorological and heavenly phenomena lead to a naturalistic science:
    She whom they call Iris, this too is by nature (pephuke) cloud
    purple, and red, and greeny-yellow to behold. (21B32)
    Xenophanes says that the star-like phenomena seen when aboard ship, which some call the Dioscuri, are cloudlets, glimmering because of their kind of motion. (A39)
    In the 1980's Alexander Mourelatos argued that Xenophanes employs an important new pattern of explanation: X is really Y, where Y reveals the true character of X. Xenophanes signals this by the use of pephuke in B32, and no doubt it (or some word like it) was there in the original of A39 as well. Xenophanes thus provides an account of a phenomenon often taken to be a sign from the divine—Iris as the messenger; the Dioscuri (St. Elmo's fire) as comfort for sailors—that reduces it to a natural occurrence.
    That meteorological phenomena are not divine is not all that Xenophanes has to say about the gods. He notes anthropomorphic tendencies in conceptions of the gods (B14: “Mortals suppose that the gods are born, and have their own dress, voice, and body;” B16: “Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and dark, Thracians, that theirs are grey-eyed and red-haired”). He also famously suggests that horses, oxen, and lions would have equine, bovine, and leonine gods (B15). Yet Xenophanes also makes positive claims about the nature of the divine, including the claim that there is a single greatest god:
    One god greatest among gods and men,
    Resembling mortals neither in body nor in thought.
    … whole [he] sees, whole [he] thinks, and whole [he] hears,
    but completely without toil he agitates all things by the
       thought of his mind.
    … always he remains in the same (state), agitated not at all,
    nor is it fitting that he come and go to different places at different times. (B23, 24, 25, 26)
    While indifferent to the affairs of human beings, Xenophanes' divine being comprehends and controls a cosmos that is infused with thinking: it is understood, organized, and managed by divine intellection. Having removed the gods as bearers of knowledge to humans, and denied that the divine takes an active interest in what mortals can or cannot know, Xenophanes asserts the conclusion to be drawn from his naturalistic interpretation of phenomena: the gods are not going to reveal anything to us; we are epistemologically autonomous and must rely on our own capacity for inquiry. That way, we “discover better,” as he says in B18, a fragment that is optimistic about the capacities of human intelligence (see Lesher 1991):
    Indeed not even from the beginning did the gods indicate all things to mortals, but, in time, inquiring, they discover better.
    This suggests that human thought can mimic divine understanding, at least to some degree. Xenophanes' own practice seems consistent with the claims of B18; his own inquiries and explanations led him to unified explanations of terrestrial and celestial phenomena. Yet B34 suggests skepticism:
    And of course the clear and certain truth no man has seen,
    nor will there be anyone who knows about the gods and what I say about all things;
    for even if, in the best case, he should chance to speak what is the case,
    all the same, he himself does not know; but opinion is found over all.
    Whether this is global or limited skepticism is controversial (Lesher 1992 and 1994 argues for a limited interpretation). Xenophanes stresses the difficulty of coming to certainty, particularly about things beyond our direct experience. Nonetheless, in B35 (a tantalizingly short fragment), Xenophanes says, “Let these thing be accepted to be like the truth” (see Bryan 2012 for a full discussion).
    Famously obscure, accused by Plato of incoherence and by Aristotle of denying the law of non-contradiction, Heraclitus writes in an aphoristic style. His apparently paradoxical claims present difficulties to any interpreter. Nevertheless, he raises important questions about knowledge and the nature of the world. The opening of Heraclitus' book refers to a “logos which holds forever.”[3]There is disagreement about exactly what Heraclitus meant by using the term logos, but it is clear from 22B1 and B2 as well as B50 and other fragments that he refers to an objective law-like principle that governs the cosmos, and which it is possible (but difficult) for humans to come to understand. There is a single order that directs all things (“all things are one” B50); this order is divine, and is sometimes connected by humans with the traditional gods (it is “both unwilling and willing to be called by the name of Zeus” B32). Just as Zeus, in the traditional view, controls everything from Olympus with a thunderbolt, so this single ordered system also steers and controls the whole cosmos, but from from within. The sign of the unchanging order of the eternal system is fire—just as fire is always changing and always the same, the logos, itself permanent, contains the unchanging account that explains the alterations and transformations of the cosmos.
    This plan or order that steers the cosmos is, itself, a rational order. This means not only that it is non-capricious and so intelligible (in the sense that humans can, at least in principle, come to understand it), it is also an intelligent system: there is an intelligent plan at work, if only in the sense of the cosmos working itself out in accordance with rational principles.[4] Consider B114:
    Those who would speak with understanding must ground themselves firmly in that which is common to all, just as a city does in its law, and even more firmly! For all human laws are nourished by one law, the divine; for it rules as far at it wishes and suffices for all, and is still more than enough.
    Heraclitus is not only claiming that human prescriptive law must harmonize with divine law, but he is also asserting that divine law encompasses both the universal laws of the cosmos itself and the particular laws of humans. The cosmos itself is an intelligent, eternal (and hence divine) system that orders and regulates itself in an intelligent way: the logos is the account of this self-regulation. We can come to grasp and understand at least part of this divine system. This is not merely because we ourselves are part of (contained in) the system, but because we have, through our capacity for intelligent thinking, the power to grasp the system as a whole, through knowing the logos. How this grasping is supposed to work is tantalizingly obscure.
    Heraclitus regards the cosmos as an ordered system like a language that can be read or heard and understood by those who are attuned to it. That language is not just the physical evidence around us (“Eyes and ears are bad witnesses to those with barbarian souls” B107); the sheer accumulation of information is not the same as wisdom (see the rebuke in 22B40, quoted above). Although the evidence of the senses is important (see B55 and other fragments on direct experience vs. hearsay), careful and thoughtful inquiry is also necessary. Those who are lovers of wisdom must be good inquirers into many things (B35; also B101: “I enquired into myself”), and must be able to grasp how the phenomena are signs or evidence of the larger order; as Heraclitus notes in B123, “nature is accustomed to hide itself,” and the evidence must be interpreted carefully. That evidence is the interplay of opposing states and forces, which Heraclitus points to by claims about the unity of opposites and the roles of strife in human life as well as in the cosmos. There are fragments that proclaim the unity or identity of opposites: the road up and down are one and the same (B60), the path of writing is both straight and crooked (B59), sea water is very pure and very foul (B61). The famous river fragments (B49a, B12, B91a) question the identity of things over time, while a number of fragments point to the relativity of value judgments (B9, B82, B102). Anaximander's orderly arrangement of just reciprocity governed by time is replaced by a system ruled by what Heraclitus calls war: “It is right to know that war is common and justice strife, and that all things come to be through strife and are so ordained” (B80). This strife or war is the set of changes and alterations that constitute the processes of the cosmos. These changes are regular and capable of being understood by one who can speak the language of the logos and thus interpret it properly (see Long, 2009). Although the evidence is confusing, it points to the deeper regularities that constitute the cosmos, just as Heraclitus' own remarks can seem obscure yet point to the truth. Heraclitus surely has his own message (and his delivery of it) in mind in B93, “The lord whose oracle is at Delphi neither speaks nor conceals, but gives a sign.”
    One of the earliest of the Greek philosophers to discuss the human soul, Heraclitus' claims about it, like his other views, are expressed enigmatically. Yet it seems fairly clear that he treats soul as the seat of emotion, movement, and intellect. B107 (quoted above) indicates that understanding is a function of soul, and in B117, the drunken man who must be led by a boy because he has lost control of his legs, and also does not know where he goes or what he does. Drunkenness is the cause of all this: because his soul has become wet its powers are dampened down and become ineffective. B118 asserts “gleam of light: dry soul, wisest and best.” This suggests that for Heraclitus, soul is a stuff that is affected by changes along the hot/cold and wet/dry continua (the gleam of light suggests a fiery, i.e., hotter soul is best). Indeed in B36, soul is listed as one of the stages of transformation of the cosmic stuffs: “it is death to souls to become water, and to water death to become earth; from earth water comes to be, from from water, soul.” Although Heraclitus says that it is only divine nature that has complete understanding (B78), his linking of fire with the logos and the divine, along with his view that the best and wisest soul is hot and dry, suggests that humans who care for their souls and search for the truth contained in the logos can overcome human ignorance and approach the understanding that Heraclitus himself has obtained. (Betegh 2007, 2009, 2013 and Dilcher 1995 both discuss the nature and importance of soul for Heraclitus; see also Granger 2000 and Kahn 1979.)

    4. Parmenides of Elea

    Parmenides, born ca. 510 BCE in the Greek colony of Elea in southern Italy (south of Naples, and now known as Velia), explores the nature of philosophical inquiry, concentrating less on knowledge or understanding (although he has views about these) than on what can be understood. Xenophanes identified genuine knowledge with the grasping of the sure and certain truth and claimed that “no man has seen” it, at least with respect to some topics (21B34); Heraclitus had asserted that divine nature, not human, has right understanding (22B78), although he implies that some humans can acquire divine-like understanding. Parmenides argues that human thought can reach genuine knowledge or understanding, and that there are certain marks or signs that act as guarantees that the goal of knowledge has been reached. A fundamental part of Parmenides' claim is that what must be (cannot not-be, as Parmenides puts it) is more knowable than what is merely contingent (what may or may not be), which can be the object only of belief.
    Parmenides gives us a poem in Homeric hexameters, narrating the journey of a young man (a kouros, in Greek) who is taken to meet a goddess who promises to teach him “all things” (28B1). The content of the story the goddess tells is not the knowledge that will allow humans, by having it, to know. Rather, the goddess gives the kouros the tools to acquire that knowledge himself:
    It is right that you learn all things,
    Both the unshaking heart of well-persuasive truth,
    and the beliefs of mortals, in which there is no true trust.
    But nevertheless, you shall learn these things too, how it were right that the things that seem be reliably, being indeed the whole of things. (B1.28–32)
    The goddess does not provide the kouros with a list of true propositions, as a body of knowledge for him to acquire, and false ones to be avoided. Rather, in teaching him how to evaluate claims about what-is, the goddess unleashes the kouros' own cognitive powers to know everything, by testing and evaluation, accepting or rejecting claims about the ultimate nature of things— for that alone is capable of being known. For Parmenides, the mark of what is known is that it is something that genuinely is, with no taint of what-is-not. That is why, for him, what-is not only is, but must be and cannot not-be. He sets this out in the key passages of B2 and B3:[5]
    Come now, and I will tell you, and you, hearing, preserve the story,
    the only routes of inquiry there are for thinking;
    the one that it is and that it cannot not be
    is the path of Persuasion (for it attends upon truth)
    the other, that it is not and that it is right that it not be,
    this I point out to you is a path wholly inscrutable
    for you could not know what is not (for it is not to be accomplished)
    nor could you point it out… For the same thing is for thinking and for being.
    The routes are methods of inquiry: keeping on the correct route will bring one to what-is, the real object of thought and understanding. Although what the goddess tells the kouros has divine sanction (hers), that is not why he should accept it. Rather, the truth she tells reveals a mark of its own truth: it is testable by reason or thought itself. In B7 the goddess warns that we must control our thought in the face of the ever-present seductions of sense-experience:
    For never shall this be forced through: that things that are not are;
    but restrain your thought from this route of inquiry,
    nor let much-experienced habit force you along this path,
    to ply an aimless eye and resounding ear
    and tongue, but judge by reasoning (logos) the much-battled testing
    spoken by me.
    The kouros himself can reach a decision or determination of the truth solely through use of his logos. Logos here means thinking or reasoning (Parmenides probably means the human capacity for thought in general). The test (restated at B8.15–16), is “is or is not?” This is not just a question of non-contradiction (which would give us coherence), but an inquiry whether or not the supposition that something is would entail, on further examination, the reality of what-is-not (which is impossible).
    The arguments of B8 demonstrate how what-is must be. In applying these arguments as tests against any suggested basic entity in the Presocratic search for ultimate causes or principles, the kouros can determine whether or not a proposed theory is acceptable. For Parmenides noos is not itself an infallible capacity. One can think well or badly; correct thinking is that which takes the correct route and so reaches what-is. The mortals on the incorrect route are thinking, but their thoughts have no real object (none that is real in the appropriate way), and so cannot be completed or perfected by reaching the truth. In B8 Parmenides sets out the criteria for the being of what-is, and then the arguments for those criteria:
    … a single account still
    remains of the route that it is; and on this route there are
    very many signs, that what-is is ungenerable and imperishable,
    a whole of a single kind, and unshaking and complete;
    nor was it nor will it be, since it is now all together
    one, cohesive. (B8.1–6)
    Any thing that genuinely is cannot be subject to coming-to-be or passing-away, must be of a single nature, and must be complete, in the sense of being unchangeably and unalterably what it is. These are signs for what any ultimate cause or principle must be like, if it is to be satisfactory as a principle, as something that can be known. The signs are adverbial, showing how what-is is (Mourelatos 2008). Only an entity which is in the complete way can be grasped and understood in its entirety by thought. McKirahan (2008) provides a thorough analysis of the arguments of B8, as does Palmer (2009).
    After laying out the arguments about what-is, the goddess turns to the route of mortals, in an account which she calls “deceptive.” Although Parmenides has been read as thus rejecting any possibility of cosmological inquiry (Barnes 1979, Owen 1960), there are persuasive interpretations that allow for justified belief about the contingent world, a world that may or may not be, and is not such that it must be (Nehamas 2002, Curd 2004, Palmer 2009). The problem of mortals is that they mistake what they perceive for what there is (and must be). As long as one realizes that the world of perception is not genuinely real, and cannot therefore be the object of knowledge, it may be possible for there to be justified belief about the cosmos. Some details of Parmenides' own cosmology are given, arguably as justified belief, in the Doxa section of the poem, and more in the testimonia from later authors. Parmenides seems to have been the first Presocratic to claim that the moon gets its light from from the sun and that the earth is spherical. Recently scholars have focused on these claims about the natural world, and have argued that Parmenides should be understood as offering an account of appearances that can and should be deemed acceptable (Palmer 2009, Cordero 2010, Graham 2013, Mourelatos 2013, Bryan 2012, Johansen forthcoming). Nevertheless, Parmenides marks a sharp distinction between being (what-is and must be) and becoming, and between knowledge and perception-based belief or opinion.

    5. The Pythagorean Tradition

    In the last quarter of the sixth century, before Parmenides' birth, Pythagoras of Samos (an Aegean island) arrived in Croton, in southern Italy. He established a community of followers who adopted his political views, which favored rule by the “better people,” and also the way of life he recommended on what seem to have been more or less philosophical bases. The traditional view has been that the aristocracy, the “better people,” generally meant the rich. But Burkert notes that as early as the 4th c. BCE there were two traditions about Pythagoras, one that meshes with the traditional view and associates Pythagoras with political tyrants, and another that credits him with rejecting tyrannies for aristocracies that might not have been grounded in wealth (Burkert 1972, 119). The Pythagorean Archytas (born late 5th century) lived in a democracy (Tarentum in southern Italy), and seems to have argued for fair and proportionate dealings between rich and poor (Huffman 2005). The Pythagorean way of life included adherence to certain prescriptions including religious rites and dietary restrictions (there is a general discussion in Kahn 2001). Detailed treatment of Pythagoras and Pythagoreanism can be found in Zhmud (2012 and 2013); an excellent collection of articles on Pythagoreanism is in Huffman (ed.) 2014.
    Like Socrates, Pythagoras wrote nothing himself, but had a great influence on those who followed him. He had a reputation for great learning and wisdom (see Empedocles 31B129), although he was treated satirically by both Xenophanes (21B7) and Heraclitus (22B40, B129). We do not know to what extent this included knowledge of mathematics, as would be suggested by the attribution to him of the famous Pythagorean theorem of geometry (Rowett 2013). The details of Pythagoras' views are unclear, but he seems to have advocated the reincarnation of the soul (a novel idea among the Greeks, also developed in Orphic religion) and the possibility of the transmigration of the human soul after death into other animal forms. Pythagorean writers after his own time stressed the mathematical structure and order of the universe. This is often attributed directly to Pythagoras (primarily because of the geometrical theorem that bears his name), but recent scholarship has shown that the evidence for attributing this mathematically-based cosmology to Pythagoras himself is convoluted and doubtful (Burkert 1972, Huffman 1993 and 2005; but see Zhmud 1997).
    What seems clear is that the early Pythagoreans conceived of nature as a structured system ordered by number (see the SEP entry on Pythagoras), and that such post-Parmenidean Pythagoreans as Philolaus (last half of the 5th century, more than a generation after Pythagoras' death) and Archytas (late 5th to early 4th century) held more complicated views about the relation between mathematics and cosmology than it is reasonable to suppose Pythagoras himself could have advanced. The Pythagorean tradition thus includes two strains. There are reports of a split in the period after Pythagoras' death between what we would term the more philosophically inclined Pythagoreans and others who primarily adopted the Pythagorean ethical, religious and political attitudes. The latter, called the acusmatici, followed the Pythagorean precepts, or acusmata (which means “things heard”). The former, the philosophical Pythagoreans (including Philolaus and Archytas), were the so-called mathematici, and while they recognized that the acusmatici were indeed Pythagoreans by virtue of accepting Pythagorean precepts, they claimed that they themselves were the true followers of Pythagoras.
    Philolaus of Croton seems to have blended the Pythagorean life with an awareness of and appreciation for the arguments of Parmenides (Huffman 1993). According to Philolaus, “Nature in the cosmos was fitted together out of unlimiteds and limiters” (44B1). These limiters and unlimiteds play the role of Parmenidean basic realities—they are and unchangingly must be what they are, and so can be known; they are joined together in a harmonia (literally, a carpenter's joint; metaphorically, a harmony), and “it was not possible for any of the things that are and are known by us to come to be, without the existence of the being of things from which the cosmos was put together” (44B6). The unlimiteds are unstructured stuffs and continua; the limiters impose structure (shape, form, mathematical structure) on the unlimiteds. Things become knowable because they are structured in this way; the structure can apparently be expressed in a numerical ratio that allows for understanding: “All things that are known have number; for without this nothing whatever could possibly be thought of or known” (44B4). Philolaus also developed a theory of the cosmos that displaced the earth from the center, replaced by what he called Hestia, the central fire (Graham 2013, 2014), and offered novel accounts of eclipses.

    6. Other Eleatics: Zeno and Melissus

    Parmenides had argued that there were strict metaphysical requirements on any object of knowledge; the later Eleatics (named for following Parmenidean doctrines rather than for strictly geographical reasons), Zeno of Elea (born ca. 490) and Melissus of Samos (fl. ca. 440), extended and explored the consequences of his arguments. Zeno paid particular attention to the contrast between the requirements of logical argument and the evidence of the senses (Vlastos 1967 is a masterly treatment of Zeno; see also McKirahan 1999 and 2005). The four famous paradoxes of motion, for which he is now and in antiquity best known, purported to show that, despite the evidence all around us, the ordinary motion of everyday experience is impossible. The paradoxes claim that motions can never be begun (the Achilles) or be completed (the Dichotomy), entail contradictions (the Moving Blocks), or are altogether impossible (the Arrow).[6] Recent philosophers of space and time (see Grünbaum 1967, articles in Salmon 2001, Huggett 1999, SEP entry on Zeno's Paradoxes) hold that the arguments are reductios of the theses that space and time are continuous (the Achilles and the Dichotomy) or discrete (the Moving Blocks and the Arrow). Consider the Dichotomy: a runner can never complete a run from point A to point B. First, the runner must move from A to a point halfway between A and B (call it C). But between A and C there is yet another halfway point (D), and the runner must first reach D. But between A and D there is yet another halfway point … and so on, ad infinitum. So the runner, starting at A, can never reach B. The argument assumes that it is impossible to pass an infinite number of points in a finite time. Similarly, Zeno produced paradoxes showing that plurality is impossible: if things are many, contradictions follow (Plato's Parmenides 127e1ff.; Zeno in 29B1, 29B2, and 29B3); there were also purported proofs that place is impossible (29A24) and that things cannot have parts (the Millet Seed, 29A29).
    Melissus, dismissed as a simple-minded thinker by Aristotle (and by some contemporary scholars as well but see Makin 2005), expands Parmenides' arguments about the nature of what-is (Palmer 2004). It is Melissus who explicitly claims that only one thing can be: if what-is is unlimited (as he thinks it is), it must be one and all alike (if there were two [in number or in character] they would be “limited against each other” 30B6). Melissus specifically argues against the empty (the void), and rejects the possibility of rearrangement (which would allow for the appearance of coming-to-be and passing-away, and of movement)—all these characteristics are incompatible with the unity of what-is (i.e., the One). Melissus thus claims that what is real is completely unlike the world that we experience: the split between appearance and reality is complete and unbridgeable.

    7. The Pluralists: Anaxagoras of Clazomenae and Empedocles of Acragas

    While Zeno and Melissus reinforced Parmenides' distinction between what-is (i.e., what must be) and what appears, other post-Parmenidean thinkers accepted Parmenides' arguments against coming-to-be and passing-away (as characterizing what-is), and about the stable nature of what is ultimately real, and argued that these arguments did not rule out the possibility of metaphysically-based (or rational) cosmology. Both Anaxagoras and Empedocles worked within the Parmenidean pattern while developing distinct cosmological systems that addressed their own particular concerns (especially in the case of Empedocles, concerns about the proper way to live).
    Anaxagoras (writing in the mid-5th c.) claims, “The Greeks [i.e., ordinary people] do not think correctly about coming-to-be and passing-away; for no thing comes to be or passes away, but is mixed together and dissociated from the things that are. And thus they would be correct to call coming-to-be mixing-together and passing-away dissociating” (59B17). What seem to be generated objects (human beings, plants, animals, the moon, the stars) are instead temporary mixtures of ingredients (such as earth, air, fire, water, hair, flesh, blood, dense, dark, rare, bright, and so on). Recent treatments of Anaxagoras (Marmodoro 2015) have suggested that the ingredients are primarily powers that manifest themselves in the mixtures produced.[7] The original state was universal mixture: “All things were together, unlimited both in amount and in smallness, for the small, too, was unlimited. And because all things were together, nothing was evident” (59B1). This mixture is set into rotary motion by the operation of Mind (Nous – B12, B13, B14; see discussions in Laks 1993, Lesher 1995, Menn 1995, Curd 2007), a separate cosmic entity that does not share in such mixture. As the rotation spreads out through the unlimited mass of indistinguishably intermingled ingredients, the rotation causes a winnowing or separating effect, and the cosmos as we know it emerges from the mixture. Moreover, not only were all things together, they are even now all together, in a different way, despite the differentiations now achieved. Everything is in everything (59B5, B6, B11), in some proportions, however small or great – this is a move to prevent even the appearance of coming-to-be from what-is-not.
    Anaxagoras marks an important theoretical step in attributing the motion of his ingredients to an independent, intelligent force (although both Plato and Aristotle were disappointed that his theory was not properly—from their point of view—teleological; on this see Sedley 2007, Curd forthcoming). The rotation begun by Mind is causally responsible for the formation of the heavens and the activities of the great masses of the earth and the water on the earth, as well as all meteorological phenomena. Insofar as the causes of the operations of the heavens and the phenomena apparent to us from day to day are the same at both the macro- and micro-level (the rotations that cause the apparent motions of the stars are the same as those that govern the cycles of weather and life and death on earth), we can infer the nature of what is real from what is apparent (Anaxagoras' scientific views are treated in Graham 2006 and 2013). Although we do not perceive all things as being together, and the move to the ultimate explanations is an inference, it is a legitimate one (“owing to their [the senses’] feebleness, we are not able to determine the truth” yet “appearances are a sight of the unseen” 59B21 and 21a).
    A younger contemporary of Anaxagoras, Empedocles, who lived in Sicily, also recognized the force of Parmenides' arguments against coming-to-be and passing-away. (Empedocles also adopts Parmenides' poetic meter in order to tell his story.) Empedocles proposes a cosmos formed of the four roots (as he calls them), earth, water, air, and fire along with the motive forces of Love and Strife. It is often claimed that, for Empedocles, Love simply produces mixture and Strife only causes separation. Empedocles' view is more complicated, for both forces mix and separate. Love unites opposed (unlike) things by pulling apart and then mixing these unlikes, while Strife sets unlikes in opposition and segregates them, hence Strife mixes like with like. Just as painters can produce fantastically lifelike scenes just by mixing colors, so the operations of Love and Strife, using just the four roots can produce “trees and men and women, and beasts and birds and water-nourished fish, and long-lived gods best in honors” (31B17). These are the things that Empedocles calls “mortal,” and he even provides recipes. 31B73 tells how Kypris (the goddess Aphrodite, i.e. love) fashions shapes (or kinds): “she moistened earth in rain, and gave it to quick fire to harden.” B96 gives a recipe for bones, while in B98 flesh and blood have the same recipe (earth, water, air, and fire in equal proportions), but differ in the refinement of the mixture.
    Like the other Presocratics, Empedocles has a cosmological theory, in his case, an unending cycle involving the competition between Love and Strife. Love overcomes the separating influence of Strife, bringing together unlikes and so preventing the clinging together of likes. The triumph of Love results in the Sphere, which is a complete mixture because the four unlike roots are as mixed (integrated) as possible. Strife breaks up the sphere by beginning to attract like to like and so pulling the mixture apart, until, when it triumphs, there is complete segregation of the roots. Love resists the separation of unlikes and the clinging together of likes, by trying to keep unlike things mixed. The cosmos as we know it is a result of intermediate phases between the two extremes of the triumph of one of the forces.[8]
    Although Empedocles gives an account of the cosmos, cosmology is not his sole interest. Both fragments and testimonia show his keen attention to questions about perception and its role in knowledge, the workings of the body, and psychology. Like the Pythagoreans, Empedocles thought that how one lived was as important as one's theoretical commitments (and that the two were intimately connected). The ancient evidence seems to suggest that Empedocles was the author of two works, commonly called in modern scholarship the Physics and the Purifications, one cosmological and the other ethico-religious. The relation between the two works has been a matter of some controversy. In the 1990s new evidence from the Strasbourg Papyrus showed unequivocally that the cosmological and ethico-religious aspects of Empedocles' thought are inextricably intertwined (Martin and Primavesi 1999, Primavesi 2008, Kingsley 1995), although commentators still disagree about whether this new evidence supports the conclusion that there was a single poem combining both.[9] The correct philosophical understanding of the physical world and the correct way to live cannot be separated from one another in Empedocles' thought (a similar attitude appears in Heraclitus); one cannot fully understand the world without living correctly.[10]Like the Pythagorean, the Empedoclean way of life included dietary restrictions and a story of transmigrating daimōns who seem to have some kind of personal identity.

    8. Presocratic Atomism

    The pluralism of Anaxagoras and Empedocles maintained the Eleatic strictures on metaphysically acceptable basic entities (things that are and must be just what they are) by adopting an irreducible pluralism of stuffs meeting these standards that could pass on their qualities to items constructed from them. Ancient atomism responded more radically: what is real is an infinite number of solid, uncuttable (atomon) units of matter. All atoms are made of the same stuff (solid matter, in itself otherwise indeterminate), differing from one another (according to Aristotle in Metaphysics 985b4-20=DK67A6) only in shape, position, arrangement. (Later sources say that atoms differ in weight; this is certainly true for post-Aristotelian atomism, but less likely for Presocratic atomism.) In addition, the Presocratic atomists, Leucippus and Democritus (Democritus was born in about 460 BCE in Abdera in Northern Greece, shortly after Socrates was born in Athens), enthusiastically endorsed the reality of the empty (or void).[11] The void is what separates atoms and allows for the differences noted above (except weight, which could not be accounted for by void, since void in an atom would make it divisible and, hence, not an atom) (Sedley 1982; see also Sedley 2008).
    Like Anaxagoras, the atomists consider all phenomenal objects and characteristics as emerging from the background mixture; in the case of atomism, the mix of atoms and void (Wardy 1988). Everything is constructed of atoms and void: the shapes of the atoms and their arrangement with respect to each other (and the intervening void) give physical objects their apparent characteristics. As Democritus says: “By convention sweet and by convention bitter, by convention hot, by convention cold, by convention color: in reality atoms and void” (68B125 = B9). For example, Theophrastus says that the flavors differ according to the shapes of the atoms that compose various objects; thus “Democritus makes sweet that which is round and quite large, astringent that which large, rough, polygonal and not rounded” (de Caus. Plant. 6.1.6 = 68A129). Simplicius reports that things composed of sharp and very fine atoms in similar positions are hot and fiery; those composed of atoms with the opposite character come to be cold and watery (in Phys. 36.3–6 = 67A14). Moreover, Theophrastus reports that the atomists explain why iron is harder than lead but lighter; it is harder because of the uneven arrangements of the atoms that make it up, lighter because it contains more void than lead. Lead, on the other hand, has less void than iron, but the even arrangement of the atoms makes lead easier to cut or to bend (de Sens. 61-63 = 68A135).
    Adopting a strong distinction between appearance and reality, and denying the accuracy of appearances, as we see him do in the above quotation, Democritus was seen by some ancient sources (especially Sextus Empiricus) as a sort of skeptic, yet the evidence is unclear. It is true that Democritus is quoted as saying, “In truth we know nothing; for truth is in the depths” (68B117). So for him, the truth is not given in the appearances. Yet, even Sextus seems to agree that Democritus allows for knowledge:
    But in the Rules [Democritus] says that there are two kinds of knowing, one through the senses and the other through the understanding. The one through the understanding he calls genuine, witnessing to its trustworthiness in deciding truth; the one through the senses he names bastard, denying it steadfastness in the discernment of what is true. He says in these words, “There are two forms of knowing, one genuine and the other bastard. To the bastard belong all these: sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch. The other, the genuine, has been separated from this” [68B11]. Then preferring the genuine to the bastard, he continues, saying, “Whenever the bastard is no longer able to see more finely nor hear nor smell nor taste nor perceive by touch, but something finer…”
    Thus Sextus suggests that the evidence of the senses, when properly interpreted by reason, can be taken as a guide to reality (the claim that “appearances are a sight of the unseen” is attributed to Democritus as well as to Anaxagoras). We just need to know how to follow this guide, through proper reasoning, so as to reach the truth—i.e., the theory of atoms and void (Lee 2005).
    In addition to fragments advancing these metaphysical and physical doctrines, there are a number of ethical fragments attributed to Democritus (but the question of authenticity looms large here); although a passage reported in John Stobaeus seems to link moderation and cheerfulness with small measured movements in the soul and says that excess and deficiencies give rise to large movements (68B191), it is unclear whether or how these claims are related to the metaphysical aspects of atomism (Vlastos 1945 and 1946, Kahn 1985b). Democritus was identified in antiquity with the idea of “good cheer” (euthumiē) as the proper guiding objective in living one's life. In this, as in other aspects of his philosophy, he may have had some influence on the formation of Epicurus' philosophy a century later.

    9. Diogenes of Apollonia and the Sophists

    In the last part of the 5th century, Diogenes of Apollonia (active after 440 BCE) revived and revised the Milesian system of cosmology, claiming that “all the things that are are alterations from the same thing and are the same thing” (64B2); he identified this single basic substance with air, like Anaximenes more than a century before (Graham 2006, Laks 2008, 2008a). Diogenes takes care to give arguments for the reality and properties of his basic principle. In B2 he says that only things that are alike can affect one another. If there were a plurality of basic substances, each differing in what Diogenes calls their “own proper nature,” there could be no interaction between them. Yet the evidence of the senses is clear: things mix and separate and interact with one another. Thus, all things must be forms of some one single thing. Like Anaxagoras, Diogenes claims that the cosmic system is ordered by intelligence, and he argues that that “which possesses intelligence (noēsis) is what human beings call air” (B5). Humans and animals live by breathing air, and are governed by it —in them air is both soul and intelligence, or mind (B4). Moreover, Diogenes argues, air governs and rules all things and is god (B5). Thus, like Anaxagoras, Diogenes has a theory grounded in intelligence, although Diogenes is more fully committed to teleological explanations, insofar as he states explicitly that intelligence (noēsis) orders things in a good way (B3). In presenting his arguments, Diogenes fulfills his own requirement for a philosophical claim. In B1 he says, “In my opinion, anyone beginning a logos (account) ought to present a starting principle (archē) that is indisputable and a style that is simple and stately.” He notes that his theory that air is soul and intelligence “will have been made clearly evident in this book” (B4).
    Theophrastus says that Diogenes was the last of the physical philosophers, the physiologoi, or “inquirers into nature,” as Aristotle called them; Diogenes Laertius gives that title to Archelaus, saying that he was the teacher of Socrates (Lives II.16-17). There was also another group of thinkers active about this time: the Sophists. Many of our views about this group have been shaped by Plato's aggressively negative assessment of them: in his dialogues Plato expressly contrasts the genuine philosopher, i.e., Socrates, with the Sophists, especially in their role as teachers of young men growing into their maturity (youths at the age when Socrates, too, engaged with them in his discussions). Modern scholarship (Woodruff and Gagarin 2008, Kerferd 1981, Guthrie 1969) has shown the diversity of their views. They were not completely uninterested in the theoretical problems that concerned others of the Presocratics. Gorgias of Leontini questioned the possibility of the certainty that Parmenides sought. In his On Nature, or On what-is-not, Gorgias claims that nothing satisfies Parmenides' requirements for what-is (Mansfeld 1985, Mourelatos 1987b, Palmer 1999, Caston 2002, Curd 2006). Protagoras, too, doubted the possibility of the strong theoretical knowledge that the Presocratics championed. The Sophists raised ethical and political questions: Does law or convention ground what is right, or is it a matter of nature? They traveled widely, sometimes serving as diplomats, and they were both entertainers and teachers. They gave public displays of rhetoric (this contrasts with Diogenes of Apollonia's comments about his book, which seems to imply a more private enterprise)[12] and took on students, teaching both the art of rhetoric and the skills necessary for succeeding in Greek political life. With the Sophists, as with Socrates, interest in ethics and political thought becomes a more prominent aspect of Greek philosophy.

    10. The Presocratic Legacy

    The range of Presocratic thought shows that the first philosophers were not merely physicists (although they were certainly that). Their interests extended to religious and ethical thought, the nature of perception and understanding, mathematics, meteorology, the nature of explanation, and the roles of matter, form, causal mechanisms, and structure in the world. Almost all the Presocratics seemed to have something to say about embryology, and fragments of Diogenes and Empedocles show a keen interest in the structures of the body; the overlap between ancient philosophy and ancient medicine is of growing interest to scholars of early Greek thought (Longrigg 1963, van der Eijk 2008). Recent discoveries, such as the Derveni Papyrus (Betegh 2004, Kouremenos et al. 2006, Janko 2001, Laks and Most 1997), show that interest in and knowledge of the early philosophers was not necessarily limited to a small audience of rationalistic intellectuals. They passed on many of what later became the basic concerns of philosophy to Plato and Aristotle, and ultimately to the whole tradition of Western philosophical thought.

    Bibliography

    Primary Sources: Texts and Translations

    • Bollack, J., 1965 and 1969, Empédocle, vol. I, 1965; vols. II and III, 1969, Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.
    • Coxon, A. H., 2009, The Fragments of Parmenides: A Critical Text with Introduction and Translation, the Ancient Testimonia, and a Commentary, edited and with new translations by Richard McKirahan, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.
    • Curd, P., 2007, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: Fragments. Text and Translation with Notes and Essays, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
    • Diels, H., 1879, Doxographi Graeci, 4th edn.; reprinted Berlin: de Gruyter, 1965.
    • Diels, H. and W. Kranz, 1974, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, three vols., original edn. 1903; reprint of 6th edn., Berlin: Weidmann.
    • Gallop, D., 1984, Parmenides of Elea: Fragments, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
    • Graham, D. W. (ed.), 2010, The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics, two volumes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Huffman, C., 1993, Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 2005, Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher, and Mathematician King, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Inwood, B., 1992, The Poem of Empedocles: A Text and Translation with an Introduction, Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Second ed., 2001.
    • Kahn, C. H., 1979, The Art and Thought of Heraclitus, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 1985a, Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology, corrected reprint of Columbia University Press edn., 1960; Philadelphia: Centrum Philadelphia; repr. Indianapolis and Cambridge, Mass.: Hackett, 1994.
    • Kirk, G. S., 1954, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Kouremenos, Theokritos; George M. Parássoglou; Kyriakos Tsantsanoglou; 2006, The Derveni Papyrus. Edited with Introduction and Commentary. Studi e testi per il “Corpus dei papiri filosofici greci e latini”, vol. 13, Florence: Casa Editrice Leo S. Olschki.
    • Laks, A., 2008, Diogène d'Apollonie: La Dernière Comologie Présocratique, 2nd edition: Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    • Lanza, D., 1966, Anassagora: Testimonianze e Frammenti, Florence: La Nuova Italia.
    • Lesher, J., 1992, Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
    • Luria, S., 1970, Democritea, Leningrad: Nauka.
    • Marcovich, M., 1967, Heraclitus: Greek Text with a Short Commentary (Editio Maior), Merida, Venezuela: Los Andes University Press.
    • Martin, A. and O. Primavesi, 1999, L'Empédocle de Strasbourg, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
    • Mouraviev, S., 1999–, Heraclitea : Édition critique complète des témoignages sur la vie et l'oeuvre d'Héraclite d'Éphèse et des vestiges de son livre et de sa pensée. 9+ vols., Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    • O'Brien, D. (with J. Frère), 1987 Le Poème de Parménide: Texte, Traduction, Essai Critique = P. Aubenque (gen. ed.), Études sur Parménide, i. Paris: J. Vrin.
    • Primavesi, O., 2008, Empedokles Physika I: Eine Rekonstruktion des zentralen Gedankegangs, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
    • Reale, G., 1970, Melisso: Testimonianze e Frammenti, Florence: La Nuova Italia.
    • Robinson, T. M., 1979, Contrasting Arguments: An Edition of the “Dissoi Logoi,”, New York: Arno Press.
    • –––, 1987, Heraclitus: Fragments, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
    • Sider, D., 2005, The Fragments of Anaxagoras: Edited with an Introduction and Commentary, 2ndedn., Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    • Sprague, R. K. (ed.), 2001, The Older Sophists, Indianapolis and Cambridge MA: Hackett Publishing; corrected reprint of 1972 edition; Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
    • Taylor, C. C. W., 1999, The Atomists: Leucippus and Democritus, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
    • Tarán, L., 1965, Parmenides, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • Wright, M. R., 1981, Empedocles: The Extant Fragments, New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Secondary Literature

    Note: Edited volumes contain collections of articles, not all of which are listed individually in this bibliography.
    • Algra, K., 1995, Concepts of Space in Greek Thought, Leiden: E.J. Brill.
    • ––– 1999, “The Beginnings of Cosmology,” in Long, 1999: 45–65.
    • Austin, S., 1986, Parmenides: Being, Bounds, and Logic, New Haven: Yale University Press.
    • –––, 2007, Parmenides and the History of Dialectic: Three Essays, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.
    • Baltussen, H., 2000, Theophrastus against the Presocratics and Plato: Peripatetic Dialectic in the, De Sensibus, Leiden and Boston: Brill.
    • Barnes, J., 1982, The Presocratic Philosophers, 2nd edition, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    • Betegh, G., 2004, The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 2007, “On the Physical Aspect of Heraclitus' Psychology,” Phronesis, 52: 3–32.
    • –––, 2009, “The Limits of Soul: Heraclitus B45 DK. Its Text and Interpretation,” in Hülz Piccone 2009: 391–414.
    • –––, 2013, “On the Physical Aspect of Heraclitus' Psychology: With New Appendices,” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 225–261.
    • Brown, L. 1994, “The verb ‘to be’ in Greek Philosophy: Some Remarks,” in S. Everson, ed., Language. Companions to Ancient Thought 3, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Brunschwig, J. and G.E.R. Lloyd, 2000, Greek Thought: A Guide to Classical Knowledge, Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    • Bryan, J., 2012, Likeness and Likelihood in the Presocratics and Plato, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Burkert, W., 1972, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, E. L. Minar, Jr. (trans.), Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    • –––, 2008, “Prehistory of Presocratic Philosophy in an Orientalizing Context,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 55–85.
    • Burnet, J., 1930, Early Greek Philosophy, 4th edn., London: Adam and Charles Black.
    • Cartledge, P., 1999, Democritus, New York: Routledge.
    • Caston, V., 2002, “Gorgias on Thought and its Objects,” in Caston and Graham 2002: 205–232.
    • Caston, V. and D. Graham (eds.), 2002, Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honor of A. P. D. Mourelatos, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Co.
    • Cherniss, H., 1935, Aristotle's Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
    • Cordero, N., 2004, By Being, It Is, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.
    • Cornelli, G, 2013 In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category, Berlin: De Gruyter.
    • Cornelli, G., R. McKirahan, and C. Macris, (eds.), 2013, On Pythagoreanism, Berlin: De Gruyter.
    • Curd, P., 2004, The Legacy of Parmenides: Eleatic Monism and Later Presocratic Thought, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998, rev. edn. Las Vegas: Parmenides Press.
    • –––, 2006, “Gorgias and the Eleatics,” in Sassi 2006, 183–200.
    • –––, 2011, “New Work on the Presocratics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 49: 1–37.
    • –––, 2013, “The Divine and the Thinkable: Toward an Account of the Intelligible Cosmos,”Rhizomata, 1: 217–247.
    • –––, forthcoming (a), “Presocratic Accounts of Perception and Cognition,” in J. Sisko, (ed.),Philosophy of Mind in Antiquity.
    • –––, forthcoming (b), “Presocratic Natural Philosophy,” in L. Taub (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek and Roman Science.
    • Curd, P. and D. H. Graham (eds.), 2008, The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press.
    • Dilcher, R., 1995, Studies in Heraclitus, Hildesheim: Georg Olms.
    • –––, 2006, “Parmenides on the Place of Mind,” in King 2006, 31–48.
    • –––, 2013, “How Not to Conceive Heraclitean Harmony,” in Sider and Obbink 2013, 263–280.
    • van der Eijk, P., 2008, “The Role of Hippocratic Medicine in the Formation of Early Greek Thought,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 385–412.
    • Frede, D. and B. Reis, (eds.), 2009, Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy, Berlin: de Gruyter.
    • von Fritz, K., 1943, “NOOS and NOEIN in the Homeric Poems,” Classical Philology, 38: 79–93.
    • –––, 1945 and 1946, “NOOS, NOEIN, and their Derivatives in Presocratic Philosophy (excluding Anaxagoras) I,” Classical Philology, 40: 223–242; and II “The Post-Parmenidean Period,” Classical Philology, 41: 12–34.
    • Furley, D., 1967, Two Studies in the Greek Atomists, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • –––, 1983, “Weight and Motion in Democritus' Theory,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 1: 193–209.
    • –––, 1987, The Greek Cosmologists, Vol. I: The Formation of the Atomic Theory and its Earliest Critics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 1989, Cosmic Problems: Essays on Greek and Roman Philosophy of Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Furley, D. J. and R.E. Allen (eds.) 1970 and 1975, Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, 2 vols., London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    • Furth, M., 1991, “A ‘Philosophical Hero?’ Anaxagoras and the Eleatics,” Oxford Studies in, Ancient Philosophy, 9: 95–129.
    • ––– 1993, “Elements of Eleatic Ontology,” in A. P. D. Mourelatos 1993, 241–270.
    • Gemelli Marciano, M. L., 2002, “Le contexe culturel des Présocratiques: adversaires et destinataires,” in Laks and Louguet, 2002: 83–114.
    • –––, 2008, “Images and Experience: at the Root of Parmenides' Aletheia,” Ancient Philosophy, 28: 83–114.
    • Gill, M. L. and P. Pellegrin (eds.), 2006, A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.
    • Graham, D. W., 1997, “Heraclitus' Criticism of Ionian Philosophy,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 15: 1–50.
    • –––, 2004, “Was Anaxagoras a Reductionist?” Ancient Philosophy, 24: 1–18.
    • –––, 2006, Explaining the Cosmos: The Ionian Tradition of Scientific Philosophy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • –––, 2013, Science Before Socrates: Parmenides, Anaxagoras, and the New Astronomy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • Granger, H., 2000, “Death's Other Kingdom: Heraclitus on the Life of the Foolish and the Wise,” Classical Philology, 95: 260–81.
    • –––, 2010, “The Proem of Parmenides' Poem,” Ancient Philosophy, 28: 1–20.
    • –––, 2013, “Early Natural Theology: The Purification of the Divine Nature,” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 163–200.
    • Gregory, A., 2007, Ancient Greek Cosmogony, London: Duckworth.
    • –––, 2013, The Presocratics and the Supernatural: Magic, Philosophy, and Science in Early Greece, London: Bloomsbury.
    • Grünbaum, A., 1967, Modern Science and Zeno's Paradoxes, Middletown: Connecticut Wesleyan University Press.
    • Guthrie, W. K. C., 1962, 1965, 1969, A History of Greek Philosophy, Vols. I, II, and III Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965.
    • Hankinson, R. J., 2008, “Reason, Cause, and Explanation in Presocratic Philosophy,” in Curd and Graham, 2008: 434–57.
    • Hasper, P. 1999, “The Foundations of Presocratic Atomism,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 27, 1–14.
    • –––, 2006, “Zeno Unlimited,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 30: 49–85.
    • –––, 2013, “Leucippus and Democritus,” in Sheffield and Warren 2013: 65–78
    • Heidel, W. A., 1906, “Qualitative Change in Pre-Socratic Philosophy,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 19 (n.s. 12): 333–379.
    • –––, 1913, “On Certain Fragments of the Pre-Socratics: Critical Notes and Elucidations,” Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 48: 681–734.
    • Hermann, A., 2004, To Think Like God. Pythagoras and Parmenides: The Origins of Philosophy, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.
    • Hölscher, U., 1970, “Anaximander and the Beginnings of Greek Philosophy,” in Furley and Allen 1975, 281–322.
    • Huffman, C. A., 1999, “The Pythagorean Tradition,” in Long 1999, 66–87.
    • –––, 2009, “The Pythagorean Conception of the Soul from Pythagoras to Philolaus,” in Frede and Reis 2009: 21–43.
    • –––, (ed.), 2014, A History of Pythagoreanism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Huggett, N. (ed.), 1999, Space from Zeno to Einstein: Classic Readings with a Contemporary Commentary, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
    • Hülz Piccone, E., (ed.), 2009, Nuevos Ensayos sobre Heráclito: Actas del Symposium Heracliteum Secundum, Mexico City: UNAM.
    • –––, 2013, “Heraclitus on Logos: Language, Rationality, and the Real,” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 281–302.
    • Hussey, E., 1972, The Presocratics, London: Duckworth.
    • –––, 1982, “Epistemology and Meaning in Heraclitus,” in M. Schfield and M. Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 33–59.
    • –––, 1999, “Heraclitus,” in Long 1999: 88–112.
    • –––, 2006, “Parmenides on Thinking,” in King 2006: 13–30.
    • Inwood, B., 1986, “Anaxagoras and Infinite Divisibility,” Illinois Classical Studies, 11: 17–33.
    • Janko, R., 2001, “The Derveni Papyrus (Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?): A New Translation,” Classical Philology, 96: 1–32.
    • Johansen, T., forthcoming, “Parmenides' Likely Story” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy.
    • Kahn, C., 1978, “Why Existence does not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 58: 323–334.
    • –––, 1985b, “Democritus and the Origins of Moral Psychology,” American Journal of Philology, 106: 1–31.
    • –––, 2001, Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans, Indianapolis: Hackett.
    • –––, 2003, “Writing Philosophy,” in H, Yunis (ed.), Written Texts and the Rise of Literate Culture, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 139–61.
    • Kerferd, G. B., 1955/56, “Gorgias on Nature or That Which Is Not,” Phronesis, 1: 3–25.
    • –––, 1969, “Anaxagoras and the Concept of Matter before Aristotle,” Bulletin of the, John Rylands Library, 52: 129–143. Reprinted in A.P.D. Mourelatos 1993: 489–503.
    • –––, 1981, The Sophistic Movement, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Keyser, P. and Georgia L. Irby-Massie (eds.), 2007, The Routledge Biographical Encyclopedia of Ancient Natural Science, Oxford: Routledge.
    • King, R. A. H., (ed.), 2006, Common to Body and Soul: Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behaviour in Greco-Roman Antiquity, Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.
    • Kingsley, P., 1995, Ancient Philosophy, Mystery, and Magic: Empedocles and Pythagorean Tradition, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    • –––, 2002, “Empedocles for the New Millennium,” Ancient Philosophy, 22: 333–413.
    • Kirk, G. S., J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield, 1983, The Presocratic Philosophers, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Laks, A., 1993, “Mind's Crisis: On Anaxagoras' NOUS,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 3 (Supplementary Volume): 19–38.
    • –––, 1999, “Soul, Sensation, and Thought,” in Long 1999: 250–70.
    • –––, 2006, Introduction à la “philosophie présocratique”, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
    • –––, 2008a, “Speculating about Diogenes of Apollonia,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 353–364.
    • Laks, A. and C. Louguet (eds.), 2002, Qu'est-ce que la Philosophie présocratique?, Lille: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion.
    • Laks, A. and G. Most (eds.), 1997, Studies on the Derveni Papyrus, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • Lee, Mi-Kyoung, 2005, Epistemology after Protagoras. Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    • Lesher, J. H., 1991, “Xenophanes on Inquiry and Discovery: An Alternative to the ‘Hymn to Progress’ Reading of Xenophanes' fragment 18,” Ancient Philosophy, 11: 229–248.
    • –––, 1994, “The Emergence of Philosophical Interest in Cognition,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12: 1–34.
    • –––, 1995, “Mind's Knowledge and Powers of Control in Anaxagoras DK B12,” Phronesis, 40: 125–142.
    • –––, 2008, “The Humanizing of Knowledge in Presocratic Thought,” in Curd and Graham, 2008, 458–484.
    • Lloyd, G. E. R., 1966, Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966; reprinted 1987 and 1992, Geo. Duckworth & Co., and Hackett Publishing Co.
    • Long, A. A., 1993, “Empedocles' Cosmic Cycle in the ‘Sixties,’” in Mourelatos 1993: 397–425.
    • –––, 2009, “Heraclitus on Measure and the Explicit Emergence of Rationality,” in Frede and Reis 2009: 87–109.
    • –––, 1996, “Parmenides on Thinking Being,” in J. Cleary, (ed.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 12, Lanham MD: University Press of America: 125–51.
    • Long, A. A. (ed.), 1999, The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Longrigg, J., 1963, “Philosophy and Medicine: Some Early Interactions,” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 67: 147–175.
    • Mackenzie, M. M., 1988, “Heraclitus and the Art of Paradox,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 6: 1–37.
    • Makin, S., 1982, “Zeno on Plurality,” Phronesis, 27: 223–238.
    • –––, 1989, “The Indivisibility of the Atom,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 71: 125–149.
    • –––, 2005, “Melissus and his Opponents: The Argument of DK 30 B 8,” Phronesis, 50: 263–88.
    • Mansfeld, J., 1964, Die Offenbarung des Parmenides and die Menschliche Welt, Assen: Van Gorcum.
    • –––, 1985, “Historical and Philosophical Aspects of Gorgias' ‘On What is Not’,” in L. Montoneri and F. Romano (eds.), Gorgia e la Sofistica: Atti del convegno internazionale, Lentini-Catania, 12-15 dicembre 1983, Siculorium Gymnasium, N.S. a38, nos. 1–2 (Catania: Università di Catania, 1985), reprinted in Mansfeld, 1990: 243–271.
    • –––, 1990, Studies in the Historiography of Greek Philosophy, Assen: Van Gorcum.
    • –––, 1999, “Sources,” in Long 1999: 22–44.
    • Mansfeld, J. and D. T. Runia, 1997, Aëtiana. The Method and Intellectual Context of a Doxographer, Vol. I: The Sources, Leiden and Boston: E. J. Brill.
    • –––, 2009, Aëtiana. The Method and Intellectual Context of a Doxographer, Vol. II: The Compendium, two parts, Leiden and Boston: E. J. Brill.
    • –––, 2010, Aëtiana. The Method and Intellectual Context of a Doxographer, Vol. III: Studies in the Doxographical Traditions of Ancient Philosophy, Leiden and Boston: E. J. Brill.
    • McCoy, J. (ed.), 2013, Early Greek Philosophy: The Presocratics and the Emergence of Reason, Washington: Catholic University Press of America.
    • McDiarmid, J. B., 1953, “Theophrastus on the Presocratic Causes,” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 61: 85–156.
    • McKirahan, R., 2005, “Zeno of Elea” in D. M. Borchert (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2ndedn.), New York: Thomson Gale, vol. 9, 871–879.
    • –––, 2008, “Signs and Arguments in Parmenides B8,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 189–229.
    • –––, 2011, Philosophy Before Socrates, 2nd edition, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.
    • Menn, S., 1995, Plato on God as Nous, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
    • Mogyoródi, E., 2002, “Xenophanes as a Philosopher: Theology and Theodicy,” in Laks and Louguet 2002, 253–286.
    • –––, 2006, “Xenophanes' Epistemology and Parmenides' Quest for Knowledge,” in M. M Sassi, 2006, 123–160.
    • Mourelatos, A. P. D., 2008, The Route of Parmenides, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing; revised and expanded edition of 1971, New Haven: Yale University Press.
    • –––, 1987a, “Quality, Structure, and Emergence in Later Presocratic Philosophy,” in J. Cleary (ed.),Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 2, Lanham, MD: University Press of America: 127–194.
    • –––, 1987b, “Gorgias on the Function of Language,” Philosophical Topics, 15: 135–70.
    • –––, 2008, “The Cloud-Astrophysics of Xenophanes and Ionian Material Monism,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 134–168.
    • –––, 2013, “Parmenides, Greek Astronomy, and Modern Scientific Realism,” in McCoy 2013: 91–112.
    • Mourelatos, A. P. D. (ed.), 1993, The Pre-Socratics, Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1974; reprinted Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • Nehamas, A., 2002, “Parmenidean Being/Heraclitean Fire,” in Caston and Graham 2002: 45–64.
    • Nussbaum, M. 1972, “Psyche in Heraclitus,” Phronesis, 17: 1–16; 153–70.
    • O'Brien, D., 1969, Empedocles' Cosmic Cycle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 1981, Theories of Weight in the Ancient World, Vol. I: Democritus on Weight and Size: An Exercise in the Reconstruction of Early Greek Philosophy, Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
    • –––, 1995, “Empedocles Revisited,” Ancient Philosophy, 15: 403–470.
    • Osborne, C., 1987a, Rethinking Early Greek Philosophy: Hippolytus of Rome and the Presocratics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
    • –––, 1987b, “Empedocles Recycled,” Classical Quarterly, 37: 24–50.
    • –––, 1998, “Was Verse the Default Form for Presocratic Philosophy?” in C. Atherton, (ed.), Form and Content in Didactic Poetry, Bari: Levante: 23–35.
    • –––, 2000, “Rummaging in the Recycling Bins of Upper Egypt: A discussion of A. Martin and O. Primavesi,” L'Empédocle de Strasbourg, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 18: 329–356.
    • –––, 2005, “Sin and Moral Responsibility in Empedocles' Cosmic Cycle” in Pierris 2005, 283–308.
    • Owen, G. E. L., 1957/58, “Zeno and the Mathematicians,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 58: 199–222; revised edn. in Owen 1986: 45–61.
    • –––, 1960, “Eleatic Questions,” Classical Quarterly, 10: 84–102. Reprinted with additional notes in Furley and Allen, vol. II: 48–81; revised edn. in Owen, 1986, 3–26.
    • –––, 1986, Logic, Science, and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    • Palmer, J., 1999, Plato's Reception of Parmenides, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    • –––, 2004, “Melissus and Parmenides,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 26: 19–54.
    • –––, 2009, Parmenides and Presocratic Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • Patterson, R; V. Karasmanis, and A. Hermann, 2012, Presocratics and Plato: Festchrift at Delphi in Honor of Charles Kahn, Las Vegas, Zurich, Athens: Parmenides Publishing.
    • Pierris, A. (ed.), 2005, The Empedoclean Kosmos: Structure, Process, and the Question of Cyclicity, Patras: Institute for Philosophical Research.
    • Popper, K. 1998, The World of Parmenides, London and New York: Routledge.
    • Primavesi, O., 2008, “Empedocles: Physical Divinity and Allegorical Myth,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 250–283.
    • Raven, J. E., 1948, Pythagoreans and Eleatics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • Riedwig, C., 2002, Pythagoras, His Life, Teaching, and Influence, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
    • Robbiano, C. 2007, Becoming Being: On Parmenides' Transformative Philosophy, Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    • Rowett, C. 2013, “Philosophy's Numerical Turn: Why the Pythagoreans' Interest in Numbers is Truly Awesome,” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 3–31.
    • Runia, D. T., 2008, “The Sources for Presocratic Philosophy,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 27–54.
    • Salmon, W. C., 2001, Zeno's Paradoxes, 2nd edn., Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
    • Sassi, M. M. (ed.), 2006, La costruzione del discorso filosofico nell' età dei Presocratici, Pisa: Edizioni della Normale.
    • Schofield, M., 1980, An Essay on Anaxagoras, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • –––, 1991, “Heraclitus' Theory of Soul and its Antecedents,” in S. Everson, (ed.), Psychology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 13–34.
    • –––, 1997, “The Ionians,” in Taylor, 1997b: 47–87.
    • Sedley, D., 1982, “Two Conceptions of Vacuum,” Phronesis, 27: 175–193.
    • –––, 1999, “Parmenides and Melissus,” in Long, 1999: 113–33.
    • –––, 2007, Creationism and its Critics in Antiquity, Berkeley: University of California Press.
    • –––, 2008, “Atomism's Eleatic Roots,” in Curd and Graham, 2008: 305–32.
    • Sheffield F. and J. Warren (eds.), 2013, Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, New York: Routledge.
    • Sider, D., 2013, “Heraclitus' Ethics” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 321–334.
    • Sider, D. and D. Obbink (eds.), 2013, Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras, Berlin: de Gruyter.
    • Solmsen, F., 1969, “The ‘Eleatic One’ in Melissus,” Mededelingen der Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afd. Letterkunds, Nieuwe Reeks 32/8: 221–233.
    • –––, 1971, “The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-examined,” Phronesis, 16: 116–41.
    • –––, 1988, “Abdera's Arguments for the Atomic Theory,” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies, 29: 59–73.
    • Sorabji, R., 1988, Matter, Space, and Motion: Theories in Antiquity and their Sequel, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
    • Stokes, M., 1971, One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy, Washington, DC: The Center for Hellenic Studies.
    • Strang, C., 1963, “The Physical Theory of Anaxagoras,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 45: 101–118.
    • Taylor, C.C.W., 1997a, “Anaxagoras and the Atomists,” in C.C.W. Taylor (ed.), 1997b 208–243.
    • –––, (ed.), 1997b, Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. I: From the Beginning to Plato, London and New York: Routledge.
    • Trépanier, S., 2003, “Empedocles on the Ultimate Symmetry of the World,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 24: 1-57.
    • –––, 2004, Empedocles: An Interpretation, New York: Routledge.
    • Vegetti, M., 1999, “Culpability, Responsibility, Cause: Philosophy, Historiography, and Medicine in the Fifth Century,” in Long, 1999: 271–89.
    • Vlastos, G., 1945 and 1946, “Ethics and Physics in Democritus,” Philosophical Review, 54: 578–592 and 55: 53–64; reprinted in Vlastos 1995: 328–350.
    • –––, 1947, “Equality and Justice in Early Greek Cosmologies,” Classical Philology, 42: 156–178; reprinted in Vlastos 1995: 57–88.
    • –––, 1950, “The Physical Theory of Anaxagoras,” Philosophical Review, 59: 31–57; reprinted in Vlastos 1995: 303–327.
    • –––, 1967, “Zeno of Elea,” in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Volume 8), New York: MacMillan, 369–379.
    • –––, 1975, “Plato's Testimony Concerning Zeno of Elea,” Journal of Hellenic Studies, 95: 136–162.
    • –––, 1995, Studies in Greek Philosophy, Vol. I: The Presocratics, D. W. Graham (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    • Warren, J., 2007, Presocratics, Tedington: Acumen.
    • –––, 2007, “Anaxagoras on Perception, Pleasure, and Pain,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 33: 19–54.
    • Wardy, R. B. B., 1988, “Eleatic Pluralism,” Archiv für, Geschichte, der Philosophie, 70: 125–146.
    • Waterfield, R., 2000, The First Philosophers, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • West, M. L., 1971, Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • White, S., 2002, “Thales and the Stars,” in Caston and Graham 2002, 3–18.
    • –––, 2008, “Milesian Measures,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 89–133.
    • Wright, M.R. 2008, “Presocratic Cosmologies,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 413–433.
    • Woodruff, P. and M. Gagarin, 2008, “The Sophists,” in Curd and Graham 2008: 365–382.
    • Zeller, E., 1923, Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer Geschichtlichen Entwicklung, W. Nestle (ed.), 7th edn., Leipzig: O. R. Reisland.
    • Zeyl, D., 1997, Encyclopedia of Classical Philosophy, Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
    • Zhmud, L., 1997, Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Religion Im Frühen Pythagoreismus, Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
    • –––, 2012, Pythagoras and the Early Pythagoreans, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    • –––, 2013, “Pythagorean Communities: From Individuals to a Collective Portrait,” in Sider and Obbink 2013: 33–52.

    No comments:

    Post a Comment